Why negating universal quantifier gives existential quantifier?











up vote
6
down vote

favorite
3












Negating a universal quantifier gives the existential quantifier, and vice versa:



$neg forall x = exists x \
neg exists x = forall x$



Why is this, and is there a proof for it (is it even possible to prove it, or is it just an axiom)? Intuitively, I would think that negating "for all" would give "none," or even "not for all," and that negating "there exists" would give "there does not exist".










share|cite|improve this question


















  • 5




    Don't forget the $lnot$ that moved past the quantifiers, $lnot forall x leadsto exists x lnot$, and $lnotexists x leadsto forall x lnot$.
    – Daniel Fischer
    Jan 31 '14 at 1:21






  • 2




    If I say "all birds can fly" and you believe I'm wrong, what are you saying (apart from any specific example)?
    – David
    Jan 31 '14 at 1:22






  • 1




    Possible duplicate of Are the quantifier negation rules in first-order logic derivable?
    – user21820
    Nov 19 at 17:21















up vote
6
down vote

favorite
3












Negating a universal quantifier gives the existential quantifier, and vice versa:



$neg forall x = exists x \
neg exists x = forall x$



Why is this, and is there a proof for it (is it even possible to prove it, or is it just an axiom)? Intuitively, I would think that negating "for all" would give "none," or even "not for all," and that negating "there exists" would give "there does not exist".










share|cite|improve this question


















  • 5




    Don't forget the $lnot$ that moved past the quantifiers, $lnot forall x leadsto exists x lnot$, and $lnotexists x leadsto forall x lnot$.
    – Daniel Fischer
    Jan 31 '14 at 1:21






  • 2




    If I say "all birds can fly" and you believe I'm wrong, what are you saying (apart from any specific example)?
    – David
    Jan 31 '14 at 1:22






  • 1




    Possible duplicate of Are the quantifier negation rules in first-order logic derivable?
    – user21820
    Nov 19 at 17:21













up vote
6
down vote

favorite
3









up vote
6
down vote

favorite
3






3





Negating a universal quantifier gives the existential quantifier, and vice versa:



$neg forall x = exists x \
neg exists x = forall x$



Why is this, and is there a proof for it (is it even possible to prove it, or is it just an axiom)? Intuitively, I would think that negating "for all" would give "none," or even "not for all," and that negating "there exists" would give "there does not exist".










share|cite|improve this question













Negating a universal quantifier gives the existential quantifier, and vice versa:



$neg forall x = exists x \
neg exists x = forall x$



Why is this, and is there a proof for it (is it even possible to prove it, or is it just an axiom)? Intuitively, I would think that negating "for all" would give "none," or even "not for all," and that negating "there exists" would give "there does not exist".







quantifiers






share|cite|improve this question













share|cite|improve this question











share|cite|improve this question




share|cite|improve this question










asked Jan 31 '14 at 1:18









George Newton

185116




185116








  • 5




    Don't forget the $lnot$ that moved past the quantifiers, $lnot forall x leadsto exists x lnot$, and $lnotexists x leadsto forall x lnot$.
    – Daniel Fischer
    Jan 31 '14 at 1:21






  • 2




    If I say "all birds can fly" and you believe I'm wrong, what are you saying (apart from any specific example)?
    – David
    Jan 31 '14 at 1:22






  • 1




    Possible duplicate of Are the quantifier negation rules in first-order logic derivable?
    – user21820
    Nov 19 at 17:21














  • 5




    Don't forget the $lnot$ that moved past the quantifiers, $lnot forall x leadsto exists x lnot$, and $lnotexists x leadsto forall x lnot$.
    – Daniel Fischer
    Jan 31 '14 at 1:21






  • 2




    If I say "all birds can fly" and you believe I'm wrong, what are you saying (apart from any specific example)?
    – David
    Jan 31 '14 at 1:22






  • 1




    Possible duplicate of Are the quantifier negation rules in first-order logic derivable?
    – user21820
    Nov 19 at 17:21








5




5




Don't forget the $lnot$ that moved past the quantifiers, $lnot forall x leadsto exists x lnot$, and $lnotexists x leadsto forall x lnot$.
– Daniel Fischer
Jan 31 '14 at 1:21




Don't forget the $lnot$ that moved past the quantifiers, $lnot forall x leadsto exists x lnot$, and $lnotexists x leadsto forall x lnot$.
– Daniel Fischer
Jan 31 '14 at 1:21




2




2




If I say "all birds can fly" and you believe I'm wrong, what are you saying (apart from any specific example)?
– David
Jan 31 '14 at 1:22




If I say "all birds can fly" and you believe I'm wrong, what are you saying (apart from any specific example)?
– David
Jan 31 '14 at 1:22




1




1




Possible duplicate of Are the quantifier negation rules in first-order logic derivable?
– user21820
Nov 19 at 17:21




Possible duplicate of Are the quantifier negation rules in first-order logic derivable?
– user21820
Nov 19 at 17:21










4 Answers
4






active

oldest

votes

















up vote
7
down vote













The following two statements are equivalent:




"It is not true that all men have red hair."



"There exists at least one man who does not have red hair."




Hence $negforall x varphi$ is the same as $exists x negvarphi$.



The following are equivalent:




"It is not true that some men have green hair."



"All men have non-green hair."




Hence $neg exists x varphi$ is the same as $forall x negvarphi$.



However, the form in which you've written them is not correct (as pointed out in Daniel Fischer's comment).






share|cite|improve this answer



















  • 3




    Your second example is badly flawed. Many men have no hair at all.
    – TonyK
    Jun 17 '15 at 22:26










  • @TonyK hahaha very true.
    – Ryan
    Jan 18 '17 at 4:59










  • that damned Law of Excluded Middle
    – Ryan
    Sep 6 '17 at 4:58


















up vote
6
down vote













I will answer in a way that will likely add confusion, but I hope shows why this type of question should not be seen as too obvious and easy. I apologise in advance.



One question that comes up is "what does it mean to assert $forall x (P(x))$ when there are infinite x?" Why do students ask such a silly question? Because one way to answer it is to say "it is a fact that all x obey P" or "it is known that all x obey P" or "it has been shown P(x) for all x" or "for every x we can prove P(x)". Something like that is what a lot of students have in mind, and when one is dealing with infinities, things like knowing or proving may never get finished.



Similarly, we can ask what it means to show $exists x (P(x))$. One way that students will often think about this is that showing that is giving a particular x that obeys P.



Now, if these are the things the student is thinking, then it certainly seems reasonable to ask the question of the OP. Even if we can assert that "it is known that not all x obey P" or worse, that "for every x we cannot prove P(x)", this does not mean we have given a particular x that obeys P! So how can we assert existence here? What if we just don't know?



Of course, the answer is that there are different, completely valid ways to answer this. On one side, you have the constructivists who will smile at these questions, pat you on the shoulder, and tell you "good questions, all" as they lead you off on explanations of the meaning of truth and accessible knowledge. On another side, you have the classicists, who will try to help this poor student understand that there is much more to truth than knowledge and proof, and try to build in that student reasons why bivalent reasoning about these kinds of things is still important and how can reach assertions of existence nonconstructively.



These are both valid paths one may walk down in the philosophy of mathematics. They offer different ways to understand the meaning of assertions, and it often seems like both sides are talking past each other when they are often just talking about different things entirely. A curious student might want to get familiar with both sides, and learn the ways each approach formal manipulation.



A noncurious student, though, should probably just learn the rule and move on. Beyond here, there be dragons.






share|cite|improve this answer





















  • @exodu5 I enjoyed that. Great post. However, I must say it doesn't explain the question much lol. Michael's answer was exactly what I was looking for. Really, the reason for my comment was to say that I liked your post and it was thought provoking for me.
    – Ryan
    Jan 18 '17 at 5:08


















up vote
3
down vote













Answer to the question in the middle of the OP: in terms of formal logic this is an axiom, or to put it better it is the definition of one quantifier in terms of the other.



For example, one may take $forall$ as an undefined symbol and then define $exists x,P(x)$ to mean $negforall x,(neg P(x))$.



So from the strictly formal point of view there is no question to answer here, it's just the definition. On the other hand, we do want logic to reflect accepted and understood modes of reasoning, so examples such as those given in other answers and comments are important.






share|cite|improve this answer




























    up vote
    1
    down vote













    This was already observed by Aristoteles in his square of opposition, looking at the contradictory path:



    enter image description here



    But my question is, is this a property of classical logic, or have non-classical logics also such quantifiers? Unfortunately, for example in inituitionistc logic, we only have the following directions which are generally valid:



    ∃x¬φ → ¬∀xφ

    ∀x¬φ → ¬∃xφ

    ¬∃xφ → ∀x¬φ



    But this direction is not generally valid, picked from the wiki page about interdefinability:



    ¬∀xφ → ∃x¬φ



    The last formula might fail since the forall might be in a possible world with a greater domain than the exists.






    share|cite|improve this answer























      Your Answer





      StackExchange.ifUsing("editor", function () {
      return StackExchange.using("mathjaxEditing", function () {
      StackExchange.MarkdownEditor.creationCallbacks.add(function (editor, postfix) {
      StackExchange.mathjaxEditing.prepareWmdForMathJax(editor, postfix, [["$", "$"], ["\\(","\\)"]]);
      });
      });
      }, "mathjax-editing");

      StackExchange.ready(function() {
      var channelOptions = {
      tags: "".split(" "),
      id: "69"
      };
      initTagRenderer("".split(" "), "".split(" "), channelOptions);

      StackExchange.using("externalEditor", function() {
      // Have to fire editor after snippets, if snippets enabled
      if (StackExchange.settings.snippets.snippetsEnabled) {
      StackExchange.using("snippets", function() {
      createEditor();
      });
      }
      else {
      createEditor();
      }
      });

      function createEditor() {
      StackExchange.prepareEditor({
      heartbeatType: 'answer',
      convertImagesToLinks: true,
      noModals: true,
      showLowRepImageUploadWarning: true,
      reputationToPostImages: 10,
      bindNavPrevention: true,
      postfix: "",
      imageUploader: {
      brandingHtml: "Powered by u003ca class="icon-imgur-white" href="https://imgur.com/"u003eu003c/au003e",
      contentPolicyHtml: "User contributions licensed under u003ca href="https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-sa/3.0/"u003ecc by-sa 3.0 with attribution requiredu003c/au003e u003ca href="https://stackoverflow.com/legal/content-policy"u003e(content policy)u003c/au003e",
      allowUrls: true
      },
      noCode: true, onDemand: true,
      discardSelector: ".discard-answer"
      ,immediatelyShowMarkdownHelp:true
      });


      }
      });














      draft saved

      draft discarded


















      StackExchange.ready(
      function () {
      StackExchange.openid.initPostLogin('.new-post-login', 'https%3a%2f%2fmath.stackexchange.com%2fquestions%2f657931%2fwhy-negating-universal-quantifier-gives-existential-quantifier%23new-answer', 'question_page');
      }
      );

      Post as a guest















      Required, but never shown

























      4 Answers
      4






      active

      oldest

      votes








      4 Answers
      4






      active

      oldest

      votes









      active

      oldest

      votes






      active

      oldest

      votes








      up vote
      7
      down vote













      The following two statements are equivalent:




      "It is not true that all men have red hair."



      "There exists at least one man who does not have red hair."




      Hence $negforall x varphi$ is the same as $exists x negvarphi$.



      The following are equivalent:




      "It is not true that some men have green hair."



      "All men have non-green hair."




      Hence $neg exists x varphi$ is the same as $forall x negvarphi$.



      However, the form in which you've written them is not correct (as pointed out in Daniel Fischer's comment).






      share|cite|improve this answer



















      • 3




        Your second example is badly flawed. Many men have no hair at all.
        – TonyK
        Jun 17 '15 at 22:26










      • @TonyK hahaha very true.
        – Ryan
        Jan 18 '17 at 4:59










      • that damned Law of Excluded Middle
        – Ryan
        Sep 6 '17 at 4:58















      up vote
      7
      down vote













      The following two statements are equivalent:




      "It is not true that all men have red hair."



      "There exists at least one man who does not have red hair."




      Hence $negforall x varphi$ is the same as $exists x negvarphi$.



      The following are equivalent:




      "It is not true that some men have green hair."



      "All men have non-green hair."




      Hence $neg exists x varphi$ is the same as $forall x negvarphi$.



      However, the form in which you've written them is not correct (as pointed out in Daniel Fischer's comment).






      share|cite|improve this answer



















      • 3




        Your second example is badly flawed. Many men have no hair at all.
        – TonyK
        Jun 17 '15 at 22:26










      • @TonyK hahaha very true.
        – Ryan
        Jan 18 '17 at 4:59










      • that damned Law of Excluded Middle
        – Ryan
        Sep 6 '17 at 4:58













      up vote
      7
      down vote










      up vote
      7
      down vote









      The following two statements are equivalent:




      "It is not true that all men have red hair."



      "There exists at least one man who does not have red hair."




      Hence $negforall x varphi$ is the same as $exists x negvarphi$.



      The following are equivalent:




      "It is not true that some men have green hair."



      "All men have non-green hair."




      Hence $neg exists x varphi$ is the same as $forall x negvarphi$.



      However, the form in which you've written them is not correct (as pointed out in Daniel Fischer's comment).






      share|cite|improve this answer














      The following two statements are equivalent:




      "It is not true that all men have red hair."



      "There exists at least one man who does not have red hair."




      Hence $negforall x varphi$ is the same as $exists x negvarphi$.



      The following are equivalent:




      "It is not true that some men have green hair."



      "All men have non-green hair."




      Hence $neg exists x varphi$ is the same as $forall x negvarphi$.



      However, the form in which you've written them is not correct (as pointed out in Daniel Fischer's comment).







      share|cite|improve this answer














      share|cite|improve this answer



      share|cite|improve this answer








      edited Aug 26 '16 at 19:33

























      answered Jan 31 '14 at 1:21









      Michael Hardy

      1




      1








      • 3




        Your second example is badly flawed. Many men have no hair at all.
        – TonyK
        Jun 17 '15 at 22:26










      • @TonyK hahaha very true.
        – Ryan
        Jan 18 '17 at 4:59










      • that damned Law of Excluded Middle
        – Ryan
        Sep 6 '17 at 4:58














      • 3




        Your second example is badly flawed. Many men have no hair at all.
        – TonyK
        Jun 17 '15 at 22:26










      • @TonyK hahaha very true.
        – Ryan
        Jan 18 '17 at 4:59










      • that damned Law of Excluded Middle
        – Ryan
        Sep 6 '17 at 4:58








      3




      3




      Your second example is badly flawed. Many men have no hair at all.
      – TonyK
      Jun 17 '15 at 22:26




      Your second example is badly flawed. Many men have no hair at all.
      – TonyK
      Jun 17 '15 at 22:26












      @TonyK hahaha very true.
      – Ryan
      Jan 18 '17 at 4:59




      @TonyK hahaha very true.
      – Ryan
      Jan 18 '17 at 4:59












      that damned Law of Excluded Middle
      – Ryan
      Sep 6 '17 at 4:58




      that damned Law of Excluded Middle
      – Ryan
      Sep 6 '17 at 4:58










      up vote
      6
      down vote













      I will answer in a way that will likely add confusion, but I hope shows why this type of question should not be seen as too obvious and easy. I apologise in advance.



      One question that comes up is "what does it mean to assert $forall x (P(x))$ when there are infinite x?" Why do students ask such a silly question? Because one way to answer it is to say "it is a fact that all x obey P" or "it is known that all x obey P" or "it has been shown P(x) for all x" or "for every x we can prove P(x)". Something like that is what a lot of students have in mind, and when one is dealing with infinities, things like knowing or proving may never get finished.



      Similarly, we can ask what it means to show $exists x (P(x))$. One way that students will often think about this is that showing that is giving a particular x that obeys P.



      Now, if these are the things the student is thinking, then it certainly seems reasonable to ask the question of the OP. Even if we can assert that "it is known that not all x obey P" or worse, that "for every x we cannot prove P(x)", this does not mean we have given a particular x that obeys P! So how can we assert existence here? What if we just don't know?



      Of course, the answer is that there are different, completely valid ways to answer this. On one side, you have the constructivists who will smile at these questions, pat you on the shoulder, and tell you "good questions, all" as they lead you off on explanations of the meaning of truth and accessible knowledge. On another side, you have the classicists, who will try to help this poor student understand that there is much more to truth than knowledge and proof, and try to build in that student reasons why bivalent reasoning about these kinds of things is still important and how can reach assertions of existence nonconstructively.



      These are both valid paths one may walk down in the philosophy of mathematics. They offer different ways to understand the meaning of assertions, and it often seems like both sides are talking past each other when they are often just talking about different things entirely. A curious student might want to get familiar with both sides, and learn the ways each approach formal manipulation.



      A noncurious student, though, should probably just learn the rule and move on. Beyond here, there be dragons.






      share|cite|improve this answer





















      • @exodu5 I enjoyed that. Great post. However, I must say it doesn't explain the question much lol. Michael's answer was exactly what I was looking for. Really, the reason for my comment was to say that I liked your post and it was thought provoking for me.
        – Ryan
        Jan 18 '17 at 5:08















      up vote
      6
      down vote













      I will answer in a way that will likely add confusion, but I hope shows why this type of question should not be seen as too obvious and easy. I apologise in advance.



      One question that comes up is "what does it mean to assert $forall x (P(x))$ when there are infinite x?" Why do students ask such a silly question? Because one way to answer it is to say "it is a fact that all x obey P" or "it is known that all x obey P" or "it has been shown P(x) for all x" or "for every x we can prove P(x)". Something like that is what a lot of students have in mind, and when one is dealing with infinities, things like knowing or proving may never get finished.



      Similarly, we can ask what it means to show $exists x (P(x))$. One way that students will often think about this is that showing that is giving a particular x that obeys P.



      Now, if these are the things the student is thinking, then it certainly seems reasonable to ask the question of the OP. Even if we can assert that "it is known that not all x obey P" or worse, that "for every x we cannot prove P(x)", this does not mean we have given a particular x that obeys P! So how can we assert existence here? What if we just don't know?



      Of course, the answer is that there are different, completely valid ways to answer this. On one side, you have the constructivists who will smile at these questions, pat you on the shoulder, and tell you "good questions, all" as they lead you off on explanations of the meaning of truth and accessible knowledge. On another side, you have the classicists, who will try to help this poor student understand that there is much more to truth than knowledge and proof, and try to build in that student reasons why bivalent reasoning about these kinds of things is still important and how can reach assertions of existence nonconstructively.



      These are both valid paths one may walk down in the philosophy of mathematics. They offer different ways to understand the meaning of assertions, and it often seems like both sides are talking past each other when they are often just talking about different things entirely. A curious student might want to get familiar with both sides, and learn the ways each approach formal manipulation.



      A noncurious student, though, should probably just learn the rule and move on. Beyond here, there be dragons.






      share|cite|improve this answer





















      • @exodu5 I enjoyed that. Great post. However, I must say it doesn't explain the question much lol. Michael's answer was exactly what I was looking for. Really, the reason for my comment was to say that I liked your post and it was thought provoking for me.
        – Ryan
        Jan 18 '17 at 5:08













      up vote
      6
      down vote










      up vote
      6
      down vote









      I will answer in a way that will likely add confusion, but I hope shows why this type of question should not be seen as too obvious and easy. I apologise in advance.



      One question that comes up is "what does it mean to assert $forall x (P(x))$ when there are infinite x?" Why do students ask such a silly question? Because one way to answer it is to say "it is a fact that all x obey P" or "it is known that all x obey P" or "it has been shown P(x) for all x" or "for every x we can prove P(x)". Something like that is what a lot of students have in mind, and when one is dealing with infinities, things like knowing or proving may never get finished.



      Similarly, we can ask what it means to show $exists x (P(x))$. One way that students will often think about this is that showing that is giving a particular x that obeys P.



      Now, if these are the things the student is thinking, then it certainly seems reasonable to ask the question of the OP. Even if we can assert that "it is known that not all x obey P" or worse, that "for every x we cannot prove P(x)", this does not mean we have given a particular x that obeys P! So how can we assert existence here? What if we just don't know?



      Of course, the answer is that there are different, completely valid ways to answer this. On one side, you have the constructivists who will smile at these questions, pat you on the shoulder, and tell you "good questions, all" as they lead you off on explanations of the meaning of truth and accessible knowledge. On another side, you have the classicists, who will try to help this poor student understand that there is much more to truth than knowledge and proof, and try to build in that student reasons why bivalent reasoning about these kinds of things is still important and how can reach assertions of existence nonconstructively.



      These are both valid paths one may walk down in the philosophy of mathematics. They offer different ways to understand the meaning of assertions, and it often seems like both sides are talking past each other when they are often just talking about different things entirely. A curious student might want to get familiar with both sides, and learn the ways each approach formal manipulation.



      A noncurious student, though, should probably just learn the rule and move on. Beyond here, there be dragons.






      share|cite|improve this answer












      I will answer in a way that will likely add confusion, but I hope shows why this type of question should not be seen as too obvious and easy. I apologise in advance.



      One question that comes up is "what does it mean to assert $forall x (P(x))$ when there are infinite x?" Why do students ask such a silly question? Because one way to answer it is to say "it is a fact that all x obey P" or "it is known that all x obey P" or "it has been shown P(x) for all x" or "for every x we can prove P(x)". Something like that is what a lot of students have in mind, and when one is dealing with infinities, things like knowing or proving may never get finished.



      Similarly, we can ask what it means to show $exists x (P(x))$. One way that students will often think about this is that showing that is giving a particular x that obeys P.



      Now, if these are the things the student is thinking, then it certainly seems reasonable to ask the question of the OP. Even if we can assert that "it is known that not all x obey P" or worse, that "for every x we cannot prove P(x)", this does not mean we have given a particular x that obeys P! So how can we assert existence here? What if we just don't know?



      Of course, the answer is that there are different, completely valid ways to answer this. On one side, you have the constructivists who will smile at these questions, pat you on the shoulder, and tell you "good questions, all" as they lead you off on explanations of the meaning of truth and accessible knowledge. On another side, you have the classicists, who will try to help this poor student understand that there is much more to truth than knowledge and proof, and try to build in that student reasons why bivalent reasoning about these kinds of things is still important and how can reach assertions of existence nonconstructively.



      These are both valid paths one may walk down in the philosophy of mathematics. They offer different ways to understand the meaning of assertions, and it often seems like both sides are talking past each other when they are often just talking about different things entirely. A curious student might want to get familiar with both sides, and learn the ways each approach formal manipulation.



      A noncurious student, though, should probably just learn the rule and move on. Beyond here, there be dragons.







      share|cite|improve this answer












      share|cite|improve this answer



      share|cite|improve this answer










      answered Jan 31 '14 at 1:53









      ex0du5

      1,163712




      1,163712












      • @exodu5 I enjoyed that. Great post. However, I must say it doesn't explain the question much lol. Michael's answer was exactly what I was looking for. Really, the reason for my comment was to say that I liked your post and it was thought provoking for me.
        – Ryan
        Jan 18 '17 at 5:08


















      • @exodu5 I enjoyed that. Great post. However, I must say it doesn't explain the question much lol. Michael's answer was exactly what I was looking for. Really, the reason for my comment was to say that I liked your post and it was thought provoking for me.
        – Ryan
        Jan 18 '17 at 5:08
















      @exodu5 I enjoyed that. Great post. However, I must say it doesn't explain the question much lol. Michael's answer was exactly what I was looking for. Really, the reason for my comment was to say that I liked your post and it was thought provoking for me.
      – Ryan
      Jan 18 '17 at 5:08




      @exodu5 I enjoyed that. Great post. However, I must say it doesn't explain the question much lol. Michael's answer was exactly what I was looking for. Really, the reason for my comment was to say that I liked your post and it was thought provoking for me.
      – Ryan
      Jan 18 '17 at 5:08










      up vote
      3
      down vote













      Answer to the question in the middle of the OP: in terms of formal logic this is an axiom, or to put it better it is the definition of one quantifier in terms of the other.



      For example, one may take $forall$ as an undefined symbol and then define $exists x,P(x)$ to mean $negforall x,(neg P(x))$.



      So from the strictly formal point of view there is no question to answer here, it's just the definition. On the other hand, we do want logic to reflect accepted and understood modes of reasoning, so examples such as those given in other answers and comments are important.






      share|cite|improve this answer

























        up vote
        3
        down vote













        Answer to the question in the middle of the OP: in terms of formal logic this is an axiom, or to put it better it is the definition of one quantifier in terms of the other.



        For example, one may take $forall$ as an undefined symbol and then define $exists x,P(x)$ to mean $negforall x,(neg P(x))$.



        So from the strictly formal point of view there is no question to answer here, it's just the definition. On the other hand, we do want logic to reflect accepted and understood modes of reasoning, so examples such as those given in other answers and comments are important.






        share|cite|improve this answer























          up vote
          3
          down vote










          up vote
          3
          down vote









          Answer to the question in the middle of the OP: in terms of formal logic this is an axiom, or to put it better it is the definition of one quantifier in terms of the other.



          For example, one may take $forall$ as an undefined symbol and then define $exists x,P(x)$ to mean $negforall x,(neg P(x))$.



          So from the strictly formal point of view there is no question to answer here, it's just the definition. On the other hand, we do want logic to reflect accepted and understood modes of reasoning, so examples such as those given in other answers and comments are important.






          share|cite|improve this answer












          Answer to the question in the middle of the OP: in terms of formal logic this is an axiom, or to put it better it is the definition of one quantifier in terms of the other.



          For example, one may take $forall$ as an undefined symbol and then define $exists x,P(x)$ to mean $negforall x,(neg P(x))$.



          So from the strictly formal point of view there is no question to answer here, it's just the definition. On the other hand, we do want logic to reflect accepted and understood modes of reasoning, so examples such as those given in other answers and comments are important.







          share|cite|improve this answer












          share|cite|improve this answer



          share|cite|improve this answer










          answered Jan 31 '14 at 1:27









          David

          67.2k663126




          67.2k663126






















              up vote
              1
              down vote













              This was already observed by Aristoteles in his square of opposition, looking at the contradictory path:



              enter image description here



              But my question is, is this a property of classical logic, or have non-classical logics also such quantifiers? Unfortunately, for example in inituitionistc logic, we only have the following directions which are generally valid:



              ∃x¬φ → ¬∀xφ

              ∀x¬φ → ¬∃xφ

              ¬∃xφ → ∀x¬φ



              But this direction is not generally valid, picked from the wiki page about interdefinability:



              ¬∀xφ → ∃x¬φ



              The last formula might fail since the forall might be in a possible world with a greater domain than the exists.






              share|cite|improve this answer



























                up vote
                1
                down vote













                This was already observed by Aristoteles in his square of opposition, looking at the contradictory path:



                enter image description here



                But my question is, is this a property of classical logic, or have non-classical logics also such quantifiers? Unfortunately, for example in inituitionistc logic, we only have the following directions which are generally valid:



                ∃x¬φ → ¬∀xφ

                ∀x¬φ → ¬∃xφ

                ¬∃xφ → ∀x¬φ



                But this direction is not generally valid, picked from the wiki page about interdefinability:



                ¬∀xφ → ∃x¬φ



                The last formula might fail since the forall might be in a possible world with a greater domain than the exists.






                share|cite|improve this answer

























                  up vote
                  1
                  down vote










                  up vote
                  1
                  down vote









                  This was already observed by Aristoteles in his square of opposition, looking at the contradictory path:



                  enter image description here



                  But my question is, is this a property of classical logic, or have non-classical logics also such quantifiers? Unfortunately, for example in inituitionistc logic, we only have the following directions which are generally valid:



                  ∃x¬φ → ¬∀xφ

                  ∀x¬φ → ¬∃xφ

                  ¬∃xφ → ∀x¬φ



                  But this direction is not generally valid, picked from the wiki page about interdefinability:



                  ¬∀xφ → ∃x¬φ



                  The last formula might fail since the forall might be in a possible world with a greater domain than the exists.






                  share|cite|improve this answer














                  This was already observed by Aristoteles in his square of opposition, looking at the contradictory path:



                  enter image description here



                  But my question is, is this a property of classical logic, or have non-classical logics also such quantifiers? Unfortunately, for example in inituitionistc logic, we only have the following directions which are generally valid:



                  ∃x¬φ → ¬∀xφ

                  ∀x¬φ → ¬∃xφ

                  ¬∃xφ → ∀x¬φ



                  But this direction is not generally valid, picked from the wiki page about interdefinability:



                  ¬∀xφ → ∃x¬φ



                  The last formula might fail since the forall might be in a possible world with a greater domain than the exists.







                  share|cite|improve this answer














                  share|cite|improve this answer



                  share|cite|improve this answer








                  edited Nov 19 at 13:48

























                  answered Jun 17 '15 at 22:17









                  j4n bur53

                  1,3991230




                  1,3991230






























                      draft saved

                      draft discarded




















































                      Thanks for contributing an answer to Mathematics Stack Exchange!


                      • Please be sure to answer the question. Provide details and share your research!

                      But avoid



                      • Asking for help, clarification, or responding to other answers.

                      • Making statements based on opinion; back them up with references or personal experience.


                      Use MathJax to format equations. MathJax reference.


                      To learn more, see our tips on writing great answers.





                      Some of your past answers have not been well-received, and you're in danger of being blocked from answering.


                      Please pay close attention to the following guidance:


                      • Please be sure to answer the question. Provide details and share your research!

                      But avoid



                      • Asking for help, clarification, or responding to other answers.

                      • Making statements based on opinion; back them up with references or personal experience.


                      To learn more, see our tips on writing great answers.




                      draft saved


                      draft discarded














                      StackExchange.ready(
                      function () {
                      StackExchange.openid.initPostLogin('.new-post-login', 'https%3a%2f%2fmath.stackexchange.com%2fquestions%2f657931%2fwhy-negating-universal-quantifier-gives-existential-quantifier%23new-answer', 'question_page');
                      }
                      );

                      Post as a guest















                      Required, but never shown





















































                      Required, but never shown














                      Required, but never shown












                      Required, but never shown







                      Required, but never shown

































                      Required, but never shown














                      Required, but never shown












                      Required, but never shown







                      Required, but never shown







                      Popular posts from this blog

                      Quarter-circle Tiles

                      build a pushdown automaton that recognizes the reverse language of a given pushdown automaton?

                      Mont Emei