Confusion about the proof of Menger's Theorem in “Introduction to Graph Theory” by Douglas West











up vote
3
down vote

favorite












The proof of Menger's Theorem in the book "Introduction to Graph Theory" by Douglas West (2nd Edition; Page 167) has been divided into two cases.



The second case assumes that




"Every minimum $x,y$-cut is $N(x)$ or $N(y)$",




where $N(x)$ denote the set of neighbors of $x$.



However, it seems that the graph for Case 2 (see below) in the illustration does not satisfy this assumption. What is going on here?



Case2










share|cite|improve this question
























  • Do you have the link to the book? I can only find solution manual: home.ku.edu.tr/mudogan/public_html/…
    – mathnoob
    Nov 22 at 12:48















up vote
3
down vote

favorite












The proof of Menger's Theorem in the book "Introduction to Graph Theory" by Douglas West (2nd Edition; Page 167) has been divided into two cases.



The second case assumes that




"Every minimum $x,y$-cut is $N(x)$ or $N(y)$",




where $N(x)$ denote the set of neighbors of $x$.



However, it seems that the graph for Case 2 (see below) in the illustration does not satisfy this assumption. What is going on here?



Case2










share|cite|improve this question
























  • Do you have the link to the book? I can only find solution manual: home.ku.edu.tr/mudogan/public_html/…
    – mathnoob
    Nov 22 at 12:48













up vote
3
down vote

favorite









up vote
3
down vote

favorite











The proof of Menger's Theorem in the book "Introduction to Graph Theory" by Douglas West (2nd Edition; Page 167) has been divided into two cases.



The second case assumes that




"Every minimum $x,y$-cut is $N(x)$ or $N(y)$",




where $N(x)$ denote the set of neighbors of $x$.



However, it seems that the graph for Case 2 (see below) in the illustration does not satisfy this assumption. What is going on here?



Case2










share|cite|improve this question















The proof of Menger's Theorem in the book "Introduction to Graph Theory" by Douglas West (2nd Edition; Page 167) has been divided into two cases.



The second case assumes that




"Every minimum $x,y$-cut is $N(x)$ or $N(y)$",




where $N(x)$ denote the set of neighbors of $x$.



However, it seems that the graph for Case 2 (see below) in the illustration does not satisfy this assumption. What is going on here?



Case2







graph-theory proof-explanation connectedness graph-connectivity






share|cite|improve this question















share|cite|improve this question













share|cite|improve this question




share|cite|improve this question








edited Nov 23 at 9:26

























asked Nov 22 at 12:36









hengxin

1,5381427




1,5381427












  • Do you have the link to the book? I can only find solution manual: home.ku.edu.tr/mudogan/public_html/…
    – mathnoob
    Nov 22 at 12:48


















  • Do you have the link to the book? I can only find solution manual: home.ku.edu.tr/mudogan/public_html/…
    – mathnoob
    Nov 22 at 12:48
















Do you have the link to the book? I can only find solution manual: home.ku.edu.tr/mudogan/public_html/…
– mathnoob
Nov 22 at 12:48




Do you have the link to the book? I can only find solution manual: home.ku.edu.tr/mudogan/public_html/…
– mathnoob
Nov 22 at 12:48










1 Answer
1






active

oldest

votes

















up vote
1
down vote



accepted










The illustrations will match up with the cases, if we change the descriptions of the cases to:



Case 1'. $G$ has a minimum $x,y$-cut $S$ not contained in $N(x) cup N(y)$.



Case 2'. Every minimum $x,y$-cut is contained in $N(x) cup N(y)$.



If we follow these descriptions, then the proof still works, because the only way we use the assumption in case 2 is to say that every vertex outside ${x} cup N(x) cup N(y) cup {y}$ is in no minimum $x,y$-cut, and this is still true in case 2'. (Since case 1' is a subcase of case 1, there is nothing to worry about there.)



In general, whenever $G$ falls under both case 1 and case 2' (that is, every minimum $x,y$-cut is contained in $N(x) cup N(y)$, but there is some minimum $x,y$-cut $S$ not equal to $N(x)$ or $N(y)$) then we can handle $G$ by the argument from either case, which is where this flexibility comes from.





Pedagogical note: when I taught this proof last year, I began by considering the case where $N(x) cap N(y) = varnothing$ and $V(G) = {x} cup N(x) cup N(y) cup {y}$, which falls under case 2' and is the case where we can apply König-Egerváry. Then I dealt with the three possibilities below:





  1. $v in N(x) cap N(y)$, which is handled in the case 2 proof. (Delete $v$, reducing $kappa(x,y)$ by $1$.)


  2. $v notin {x} cup N(x) cup N(y) cup {y}$, but $v$ is not part of any minimum $x,y$-cut, which is also handled in the case 2 proof. (Delete $v$, not changing $kappa(x,y)$.)

  3. There is a minimum $x,y$-cut $S$ not contained in $N(x) cup N(y)$. (This is case 1', and we can apply the case 1 proof.)


In some sense, this is the logical progression: we apply König-Egerváry for some cases, and then show that all other cases can be reduced to smaller ones.






share|cite|improve this answer





















    Your Answer





    StackExchange.ifUsing("editor", function () {
    return StackExchange.using("mathjaxEditing", function () {
    StackExchange.MarkdownEditor.creationCallbacks.add(function (editor, postfix) {
    StackExchange.mathjaxEditing.prepareWmdForMathJax(editor, postfix, [["$", "$"], ["\\(","\\)"]]);
    });
    });
    }, "mathjax-editing");

    StackExchange.ready(function() {
    var channelOptions = {
    tags: "".split(" "),
    id: "69"
    };
    initTagRenderer("".split(" "), "".split(" "), channelOptions);

    StackExchange.using("externalEditor", function() {
    // Have to fire editor after snippets, if snippets enabled
    if (StackExchange.settings.snippets.snippetsEnabled) {
    StackExchange.using("snippets", function() {
    createEditor();
    });
    }
    else {
    createEditor();
    }
    });

    function createEditor() {
    StackExchange.prepareEditor({
    heartbeatType: 'answer',
    convertImagesToLinks: true,
    noModals: true,
    showLowRepImageUploadWarning: true,
    reputationToPostImages: 10,
    bindNavPrevention: true,
    postfix: "",
    imageUploader: {
    brandingHtml: "Powered by u003ca class="icon-imgur-white" href="https://imgur.com/"u003eu003c/au003e",
    contentPolicyHtml: "User contributions licensed under u003ca href="https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-sa/3.0/"u003ecc by-sa 3.0 with attribution requiredu003c/au003e u003ca href="https://stackoverflow.com/legal/content-policy"u003e(content policy)u003c/au003e",
    allowUrls: true
    },
    noCode: true, onDemand: true,
    discardSelector: ".discard-answer"
    ,immediatelyShowMarkdownHelp:true
    });


    }
    });














    draft saved

    draft discarded


















    StackExchange.ready(
    function () {
    StackExchange.openid.initPostLogin('.new-post-login', 'https%3a%2f%2fmath.stackexchange.com%2fquestions%2f3009077%2fconfusion-about-the-proof-of-mengers-theorem-in-introduction-to-graph-theory%23new-answer', 'question_page');
    }
    );

    Post as a guest















    Required, but never shown

























    1 Answer
    1






    active

    oldest

    votes








    1 Answer
    1






    active

    oldest

    votes









    active

    oldest

    votes






    active

    oldest

    votes








    up vote
    1
    down vote



    accepted










    The illustrations will match up with the cases, if we change the descriptions of the cases to:



    Case 1'. $G$ has a minimum $x,y$-cut $S$ not contained in $N(x) cup N(y)$.



    Case 2'. Every minimum $x,y$-cut is contained in $N(x) cup N(y)$.



    If we follow these descriptions, then the proof still works, because the only way we use the assumption in case 2 is to say that every vertex outside ${x} cup N(x) cup N(y) cup {y}$ is in no minimum $x,y$-cut, and this is still true in case 2'. (Since case 1' is a subcase of case 1, there is nothing to worry about there.)



    In general, whenever $G$ falls under both case 1 and case 2' (that is, every minimum $x,y$-cut is contained in $N(x) cup N(y)$, but there is some minimum $x,y$-cut $S$ not equal to $N(x)$ or $N(y)$) then we can handle $G$ by the argument from either case, which is where this flexibility comes from.





    Pedagogical note: when I taught this proof last year, I began by considering the case where $N(x) cap N(y) = varnothing$ and $V(G) = {x} cup N(x) cup N(y) cup {y}$, which falls under case 2' and is the case where we can apply König-Egerváry. Then I dealt with the three possibilities below:





    1. $v in N(x) cap N(y)$, which is handled in the case 2 proof. (Delete $v$, reducing $kappa(x,y)$ by $1$.)


    2. $v notin {x} cup N(x) cup N(y) cup {y}$, but $v$ is not part of any minimum $x,y$-cut, which is also handled in the case 2 proof. (Delete $v$, not changing $kappa(x,y)$.)

    3. There is a minimum $x,y$-cut $S$ not contained in $N(x) cup N(y)$. (This is case 1', and we can apply the case 1 proof.)


    In some sense, this is the logical progression: we apply König-Egerváry for some cases, and then show that all other cases can be reduced to smaller ones.






    share|cite|improve this answer

























      up vote
      1
      down vote



      accepted










      The illustrations will match up with the cases, if we change the descriptions of the cases to:



      Case 1'. $G$ has a minimum $x,y$-cut $S$ not contained in $N(x) cup N(y)$.



      Case 2'. Every minimum $x,y$-cut is contained in $N(x) cup N(y)$.



      If we follow these descriptions, then the proof still works, because the only way we use the assumption in case 2 is to say that every vertex outside ${x} cup N(x) cup N(y) cup {y}$ is in no minimum $x,y$-cut, and this is still true in case 2'. (Since case 1' is a subcase of case 1, there is nothing to worry about there.)



      In general, whenever $G$ falls under both case 1 and case 2' (that is, every minimum $x,y$-cut is contained in $N(x) cup N(y)$, but there is some minimum $x,y$-cut $S$ not equal to $N(x)$ or $N(y)$) then we can handle $G$ by the argument from either case, which is where this flexibility comes from.





      Pedagogical note: when I taught this proof last year, I began by considering the case where $N(x) cap N(y) = varnothing$ and $V(G) = {x} cup N(x) cup N(y) cup {y}$, which falls under case 2' and is the case where we can apply König-Egerváry. Then I dealt with the three possibilities below:





      1. $v in N(x) cap N(y)$, which is handled in the case 2 proof. (Delete $v$, reducing $kappa(x,y)$ by $1$.)


      2. $v notin {x} cup N(x) cup N(y) cup {y}$, but $v$ is not part of any minimum $x,y$-cut, which is also handled in the case 2 proof. (Delete $v$, not changing $kappa(x,y)$.)

      3. There is a minimum $x,y$-cut $S$ not contained in $N(x) cup N(y)$. (This is case 1', and we can apply the case 1 proof.)


      In some sense, this is the logical progression: we apply König-Egerváry for some cases, and then show that all other cases can be reduced to smaller ones.






      share|cite|improve this answer























        up vote
        1
        down vote



        accepted







        up vote
        1
        down vote



        accepted






        The illustrations will match up with the cases, if we change the descriptions of the cases to:



        Case 1'. $G$ has a minimum $x,y$-cut $S$ not contained in $N(x) cup N(y)$.



        Case 2'. Every minimum $x,y$-cut is contained in $N(x) cup N(y)$.



        If we follow these descriptions, then the proof still works, because the only way we use the assumption in case 2 is to say that every vertex outside ${x} cup N(x) cup N(y) cup {y}$ is in no minimum $x,y$-cut, and this is still true in case 2'. (Since case 1' is a subcase of case 1, there is nothing to worry about there.)



        In general, whenever $G$ falls under both case 1 and case 2' (that is, every minimum $x,y$-cut is contained in $N(x) cup N(y)$, but there is some minimum $x,y$-cut $S$ not equal to $N(x)$ or $N(y)$) then we can handle $G$ by the argument from either case, which is where this flexibility comes from.





        Pedagogical note: when I taught this proof last year, I began by considering the case where $N(x) cap N(y) = varnothing$ and $V(G) = {x} cup N(x) cup N(y) cup {y}$, which falls under case 2' and is the case where we can apply König-Egerváry. Then I dealt with the three possibilities below:





        1. $v in N(x) cap N(y)$, which is handled in the case 2 proof. (Delete $v$, reducing $kappa(x,y)$ by $1$.)


        2. $v notin {x} cup N(x) cup N(y) cup {y}$, but $v$ is not part of any minimum $x,y$-cut, which is also handled in the case 2 proof. (Delete $v$, not changing $kappa(x,y)$.)

        3. There is a minimum $x,y$-cut $S$ not contained in $N(x) cup N(y)$. (This is case 1', and we can apply the case 1 proof.)


        In some sense, this is the logical progression: we apply König-Egerváry for some cases, and then show that all other cases can be reduced to smaller ones.






        share|cite|improve this answer












        The illustrations will match up with the cases, if we change the descriptions of the cases to:



        Case 1'. $G$ has a minimum $x,y$-cut $S$ not contained in $N(x) cup N(y)$.



        Case 2'. Every minimum $x,y$-cut is contained in $N(x) cup N(y)$.



        If we follow these descriptions, then the proof still works, because the only way we use the assumption in case 2 is to say that every vertex outside ${x} cup N(x) cup N(y) cup {y}$ is in no minimum $x,y$-cut, and this is still true in case 2'. (Since case 1' is a subcase of case 1, there is nothing to worry about there.)



        In general, whenever $G$ falls under both case 1 and case 2' (that is, every minimum $x,y$-cut is contained in $N(x) cup N(y)$, but there is some minimum $x,y$-cut $S$ not equal to $N(x)$ or $N(y)$) then we can handle $G$ by the argument from either case, which is where this flexibility comes from.





        Pedagogical note: when I taught this proof last year, I began by considering the case where $N(x) cap N(y) = varnothing$ and $V(G) = {x} cup N(x) cup N(y) cup {y}$, which falls under case 2' and is the case where we can apply König-Egerváry. Then I dealt with the three possibilities below:





        1. $v in N(x) cap N(y)$, which is handled in the case 2 proof. (Delete $v$, reducing $kappa(x,y)$ by $1$.)


        2. $v notin {x} cup N(x) cup N(y) cup {y}$, but $v$ is not part of any minimum $x,y$-cut, which is also handled in the case 2 proof. (Delete $v$, not changing $kappa(x,y)$.)

        3. There is a minimum $x,y$-cut $S$ not contained in $N(x) cup N(y)$. (This is case 1', and we can apply the case 1 proof.)


        In some sense, this is the logical progression: we apply König-Egerváry for some cases, and then show that all other cases can be reduced to smaller ones.







        share|cite|improve this answer












        share|cite|improve this answer



        share|cite|improve this answer










        answered Nov 23 at 18:16









        Misha Lavrov

        43.1k555103




        43.1k555103






























            draft saved

            draft discarded




















































            Thanks for contributing an answer to Mathematics Stack Exchange!


            • Please be sure to answer the question. Provide details and share your research!

            But avoid



            • Asking for help, clarification, or responding to other answers.

            • Making statements based on opinion; back them up with references or personal experience.


            Use MathJax to format equations. MathJax reference.


            To learn more, see our tips on writing great answers.





            Some of your past answers have not been well-received, and you're in danger of being blocked from answering.


            Please pay close attention to the following guidance:


            • Please be sure to answer the question. Provide details and share your research!

            But avoid



            • Asking for help, clarification, or responding to other answers.

            • Making statements based on opinion; back them up with references or personal experience.


            To learn more, see our tips on writing great answers.




            draft saved


            draft discarded














            StackExchange.ready(
            function () {
            StackExchange.openid.initPostLogin('.new-post-login', 'https%3a%2f%2fmath.stackexchange.com%2fquestions%2f3009077%2fconfusion-about-the-proof-of-mengers-theorem-in-introduction-to-graph-theory%23new-answer', 'question_page');
            }
            );

            Post as a guest















            Required, but never shown





















































            Required, but never shown














            Required, but never shown












            Required, but never shown







            Required, but never shown

































            Required, but never shown














            Required, but never shown












            Required, but never shown







            Required, but never shown







            Popular posts from this blog

            Ellipse (mathématiques)

            Quarter-circle Tiles

            Mont Emei