What is wrong with this argument? $R/I approx R$












0












$begingroup$


Let $I subset R$ be an ideal of $R$. Define $pi(a + I) = a$ with $a in R$, so $pi: R/I to R$



Then $ker pi = I = bar{0} in R/I$ and this is clearly onto so it is an isomorphism. So this map says $R$ is always isomorphic to its quotient. Isn't there something not right about this argument? Or is this just a simple trivialization of the correspondence property?



Suppose we have the containment of ideals $I subset A subset R$



Then the correspondence theorem say $I subset A subset R stackrel{pi}leftrightsquigarrow I subset A/I subset R/I$



So considering this, set $A = R$, then $R subset R$ is an ideal of itself and so is $R/I subset R/I$, we get what I wrote previously?



Why am I asking this? It is because I was working several problems in Dummit chapter 7.4 and at least half of them could be answered by this without writing much more, but I feel like I m cheating my way here.



Here is one that made me wrote this question




If $R$ is commutative (with $1$) then if $P$ is a prime ideal of $R$ with no zero divisors, then $R$ is integral domain.




$P$ is prime so $R/P$ is integral domain. By the correspondence $R/P approx R$. So $P$ having no zero divisors seem to play no role.










share|cite|improve this question









$endgroup$








  • 4




    $begingroup$
    Your mapping $pi$ isn't well defined.
    $endgroup$
    – Nathanael Skrepek
    Dec 21 '18 at 11:08
















0












$begingroup$


Let $I subset R$ be an ideal of $R$. Define $pi(a + I) = a$ with $a in R$, so $pi: R/I to R$



Then $ker pi = I = bar{0} in R/I$ and this is clearly onto so it is an isomorphism. So this map says $R$ is always isomorphic to its quotient. Isn't there something not right about this argument? Or is this just a simple trivialization of the correspondence property?



Suppose we have the containment of ideals $I subset A subset R$



Then the correspondence theorem say $I subset A subset R stackrel{pi}leftrightsquigarrow I subset A/I subset R/I$



So considering this, set $A = R$, then $R subset R$ is an ideal of itself and so is $R/I subset R/I$, we get what I wrote previously?



Why am I asking this? It is because I was working several problems in Dummit chapter 7.4 and at least half of them could be answered by this without writing much more, but I feel like I m cheating my way here.



Here is one that made me wrote this question




If $R$ is commutative (with $1$) then if $P$ is a prime ideal of $R$ with no zero divisors, then $R$ is integral domain.




$P$ is prime so $R/P$ is integral domain. By the correspondence $R/P approx R$. So $P$ having no zero divisors seem to play no role.










share|cite|improve this question









$endgroup$








  • 4




    $begingroup$
    Your mapping $pi$ isn't well defined.
    $endgroup$
    – Nathanael Skrepek
    Dec 21 '18 at 11:08














0












0








0





$begingroup$


Let $I subset R$ be an ideal of $R$. Define $pi(a + I) = a$ with $a in R$, so $pi: R/I to R$



Then $ker pi = I = bar{0} in R/I$ and this is clearly onto so it is an isomorphism. So this map says $R$ is always isomorphic to its quotient. Isn't there something not right about this argument? Or is this just a simple trivialization of the correspondence property?



Suppose we have the containment of ideals $I subset A subset R$



Then the correspondence theorem say $I subset A subset R stackrel{pi}leftrightsquigarrow I subset A/I subset R/I$



So considering this, set $A = R$, then $R subset R$ is an ideal of itself and so is $R/I subset R/I$, we get what I wrote previously?



Why am I asking this? It is because I was working several problems in Dummit chapter 7.4 and at least half of them could be answered by this without writing much more, but I feel like I m cheating my way here.



Here is one that made me wrote this question




If $R$ is commutative (with $1$) then if $P$ is a prime ideal of $R$ with no zero divisors, then $R$ is integral domain.




$P$ is prime so $R/P$ is integral domain. By the correspondence $R/P approx R$. So $P$ having no zero divisors seem to play no role.










share|cite|improve this question









$endgroup$




Let $I subset R$ be an ideal of $R$. Define $pi(a + I) = a$ with $a in R$, so $pi: R/I to R$



Then $ker pi = I = bar{0} in R/I$ and this is clearly onto so it is an isomorphism. So this map says $R$ is always isomorphic to its quotient. Isn't there something not right about this argument? Or is this just a simple trivialization of the correspondence property?



Suppose we have the containment of ideals $I subset A subset R$



Then the correspondence theorem say $I subset A subset R stackrel{pi}leftrightsquigarrow I subset A/I subset R/I$



So considering this, set $A = R$, then $R subset R$ is an ideal of itself and so is $R/I subset R/I$, we get what I wrote previously?



Why am I asking this? It is because I was working several problems in Dummit chapter 7.4 and at least half of them could be answered by this without writing much more, but I feel like I m cheating my way here.



Here is one that made me wrote this question




If $R$ is commutative (with $1$) then if $P$ is a prime ideal of $R$ with no zero divisors, then $R$ is integral domain.




$P$ is prime so $R/P$ is integral domain. By the correspondence $R/P approx R$. So $P$ having no zero divisors seem to play no role.







abstract-algebra proof-verification






share|cite|improve this question













share|cite|improve this question











share|cite|improve this question




share|cite|improve this question










asked Dec 21 '18 at 11:05









HawkHawk

5,5251139105




5,5251139105








  • 4




    $begingroup$
    Your mapping $pi$ isn't well defined.
    $endgroup$
    – Nathanael Skrepek
    Dec 21 '18 at 11:08














  • 4




    $begingroup$
    Your mapping $pi$ isn't well defined.
    $endgroup$
    – Nathanael Skrepek
    Dec 21 '18 at 11:08








4




4




$begingroup$
Your mapping $pi$ isn't well defined.
$endgroup$
– Nathanael Skrepek
Dec 21 '18 at 11:08




$begingroup$
Your mapping $pi$ isn't well defined.
$endgroup$
– Nathanael Skrepek
Dec 21 '18 at 11:08










3 Answers
3






active

oldest

votes


















2












$begingroup$

Your $pi$ is not a function in general. For example consider $R=mathbb{Z}$ and $I=2mathbb{Z}$. Then $0+2mathbb{Z}=2+2mathbb{Z}$. So what is $pi(0+2mathbb{Z})=pi(2+2mathbb{Z})$? Is it $0$ or $2$?



Of course you can arbitrarly choose for example $pi(0+2mathbb{Z}):= 0$ (and therefore $pi(2+2mathbb{Z})= 0$) and so on for every coset but then you will find out that $pi$ is no longer a homomorphism. Indeed, let's simplify notation, I will use $[x]$ instead of $x+I$. In our case $R/I={[0],[1]}$. Note that we have $[1]+[1]=[0]$. Put for example $pi([0])=0$ and $pi([1])=1$. Then



$$pi([1]+[1])=pi([0])=0$$
$$pi([1])+pi([1])=1+1=2$$



and so $pi$ is not a homomorphism. And in this particular case there is no way to fix that. The only choice of values making $phi$ a homomorphism is $pi([x])=0$. Not to mention that $R/I$ has two elements while $R$ is infinite so there's no chance for $pi$ to be surjective.



So as you can see there are no shortcuts. Also the existence of an isomorphism $R/Isimeq R$ for $Ineq 0$ is a very rare situation. First of all if $R$ is nontrivial then $R/R$ is trivial. If you are looking for an example of proper ideal then consider $R$ which is not simple (so it has a proper, nontrivial ideal). Then there's always a proper quotient $R/I$ not isomorphic to $R$, namely for any maximal ideal $I$.






share|cite|improve this answer











$endgroup$













  • $begingroup$
    So after writing out a lot of stuff, I just came to the conclusion that maps going from the quotient $R/I$ to $R$ usually come with a lot of problems as opposed to defining $R to R/I$.
    $endgroup$
    – Hawk
    Dec 21 '18 at 12:30










  • $begingroup$
    @Hawk yes, the situation is not symmetric at all.
    $endgroup$
    – freakish
    Dec 21 '18 at 12:31










  • $begingroup$
    No what i mean is that if I had defined it $pi: R to R/I$, it would be easier to prove it is an isomorphism and to identify the problems, which in this case is well-definedness.
    $endgroup$
    – Hawk
    Dec 21 '18 at 12:33



















1












$begingroup$

Your function $pi$ is only well-defined if $I$ is the ideal ${0}$. E.g., with $R = Bbb{Z}$ and $I = 2Bbb{Z}$, we have $1 + I = 3 + I$, so if $pi(a + I) = a $, we would have to have $1 = 3$, which holds in $R/I$, but does not hold in $R$.






share|cite|improve this answer









$endgroup$





















    0












    $begingroup$

    For each $ain R$ there are several $bin R$ such that $a+I=b+I$ (unless $I={0}$ in the first place). So it is unclear what $a$ you are referring to.






    share|cite|improve this answer











    $endgroup$













      Your Answer





      StackExchange.ifUsing("editor", function () {
      return StackExchange.using("mathjaxEditing", function () {
      StackExchange.MarkdownEditor.creationCallbacks.add(function (editor, postfix) {
      StackExchange.mathjaxEditing.prepareWmdForMathJax(editor, postfix, [["$", "$"], ["\\(","\\)"]]);
      });
      });
      }, "mathjax-editing");

      StackExchange.ready(function() {
      var channelOptions = {
      tags: "".split(" "),
      id: "69"
      };
      initTagRenderer("".split(" "), "".split(" "), channelOptions);

      StackExchange.using("externalEditor", function() {
      // Have to fire editor after snippets, if snippets enabled
      if (StackExchange.settings.snippets.snippetsEnabled) {
      StackExchange.using("snippets", function() {
      createEditor();
      });
      }
      else {
      createEditor();
      }
      });

      function createEditor() {
      StackExchange.prepareEditor({
      heartbeatType: 'answer',
      autoActivateHeartbeat: false,
      convertImagesToLinks: true,
      noModals: true,
      showLowRepImageUploadWarning: true,
      reputationToPostImages: 10,
      bindNavPrevention: true,
      postfix: "",
      imageUploader: {
      brandingHtml: "Powered by u003ca class="icon-imgur-white" href="https://imgur.com/"u003eu003c/au003e",
      contentPolicyHtml: "User contributions licensed under u003ca href="https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-sa/3.0/"u003ecc by-sa 3.0 with attribution requiredu003c/au003e u003ca href="https://stackoverflow.com/legal/content-policy"u003e(content policy)u003c/au003e",
      allowUrls: true
      },
      noCode: true, onDemand: true,
      discardSelector: ".discard-answer"
      ,immediatelyShowMarkdownHelp:true
      });


      }
      });














      draft saved

      draft discarded


















      StackExchange.ready(
      function () {
      StackExchange.openid.initPostLogin('.new-post-login', 'https%3a%2f%2fmath.stackexchange.com%2fquestions%2f3048398%2fwhat-is-wrong-with-this-argument-r-i-approx-r%23new-answer', 'question_page');
      }
      );

      Post as a guest















      Required, but never shown

























      3 Answers
      3






      active

      oldest

      votes








      3 Answers
      3






      active

      oldest

      votes









      active

      oldest

      votes






      active

      oldest

      votes









      2












      $begingroup$

      Your $pi$ is not a function in general. For example consider $R=mathbb{Z}$ and $I=2mathbb{Z}$. Then $0+2mathbb{Z}=2+2mathbb{Z}$. So what is $pi(0+2mathbb{Z})=pi(2+2mathbb{Z})$? Is it $0$ or $2$?



      Of course you can arbitrarly choose for example $pi(0+2mathbb{Z}):= 0$ (and therefore $pi(2+2mathbb{Z})= 0$) and so on for every coset but then you will find out that $pi$ is no longer a homomorphism. Indeed, let's simplify notation, I will use $[x]$ instead of $x+I$. In our case $R/I={[0],[1]}$. Note that we have $[1]+[1]=[0]$. Put for example $pi([0])=0$ and $pi([1])=1$. Then



      $$pi([1]+[1])=pi([0])=0$$
      $$pi([1])+pi([1])=1+1=2$$



      and so $pi$ is not a homomorphism. And in this particular case there is no way to fix that. The only choice of values making $phi$ a homomorphism is $pi([x])=0$. Not to mention that $R/I$ has two elements while $R$ is infinite so there's no chance for $pi$ to be surjective.



      So as you can see there are no shortcuts. Also the existence of an isomorphism $R/Isimeq R$ for $Ineq 0$ is a very rare situation. First of all if $R$ is nontrivial then $R/R$ is trivial. If you are looking for an example of proper ideal then consider $R$ which is not simple (so it has a proper, nontrivial ideal). Then there's always a proper quotient $R/I$ not isomorphic to $R$, namely for any maximal ideal $I$.






      share|cite|improve this answer











      $endgroup$













      • $begingroup$
        So after writing out a lot of stuff, I just came to the conclusion that maps going from the quotient $R/I$ to $R$ usually come with a lot of problems as opposed to defining $R to R/I$.
        $endgroup$
        – Hawk
        Dec 21 '18 at 12:30










      • $begingroup$
        @Hawk yes, the situation is not symmetric at all.
        $endgroup$
        – freakish
        Dec 21 '18 at 12:31










      • $begingroup$
        No what i mean is that if I had defined it $pi: R to R/I$, it would be easier to prove it is an isomorphism and to identify the problems, which in this case is well-definedness.
        $endgroup$
        – Hawk
        Dec 21 '18 at 12:33
















      2












      $begingroup$

      Your $pi$ is not a function in general. For example consider $R=mathbb{Z}$ and $I=2mathbb{Z}$. Then $0+2mathbb{Z}=2+2mathbb{Z}$. So what is $pi(0+2mathbb{Z})=pi(2+2mathbb{Z})$? Is it $0$ or $2$?



      Of course you can arbitrarly choose for example $pi(0+2mathbb{Z}):= 0$ (and therefore $pi(2+2mathbb{Z})= 0$) and so on for every coset but then you will find out that $pi$ is no longer a homomorphism. Indeed, let's simplify notation, I will use $[x]$ instead of $x+I$. In our case $R/I={[0],[1]}$. Note that we have $[1]+[1]=[0]$. Put for example $pi([0])=0$ and $pi([1])=1$. Then



      $$pi([1]+[1])=pi([0])=0$$
      $$pi([1])+pi([1])=1+1=2$$



      and so $pi$ is not a homomorphism. And in this particular case there is no way to fix that. The only choice of values making $phi$ a homomorphism is $pi([x])=0$. Not to mention that $R/I$ has two elements while $R$ is infinite so there's no chance for $pi$ to be surjective.



      So as you can see there are no shortcuts. Also the existence of an isomorphism $R/Isimeq R$ for $Ineq 0$ is a very rare situation. First of all if $R$ is nontrivial then $R/R$ is trivial. If you are looking for an example of proper ideal then consider $R$ which is not simple (so it has a proper, nontrivial ideal). Then there's always a proper quotient $R/I$ not isomorphic to $R$, namely for any maximal ideal $I$.






      share|cite|improve this answer











      $endgroup$













      • $begingroup$
        So after writing out a lot of stuff, I just came to the conclusion that maps going from the quotient $R/I$ to $R$ usually come with a lot of problems as opposed to defining $R to R/I$.
        $endgroup$
        – Hawk
        Dec 21 '18 at 12:30










      • $begingroup$
        @Hawk yes, the situation is not symmetric at all.
        $endgroup$
        – freakish
        Dec 21 '18 at 12:31










      • $begingroup$
        No what i mean is that if I had defined it $pi: R to R/I$, it would be easier to prove it is an isomorphism and to identify the problems, which in this case is well-definedness.
        $endgroup$
        – Hawk
        Dec 21 '18 at 12:33














      2












      2








      2





      $begingroup$

      Your $pi$ is not a function in general. For example consider $R=mathbb{Z}$ and $I=2mathbb{Z}$. Then $0+2mathbb{Z}=2+2mathbb{Z}$. So what is $pi(0+2mathbb{Z})=pi(2+2mathbb{Z})$? Is it $0$ or $2$?



      Of course you can arbitrarly choose for example $pi(0+2mathbb{Z}):= 0$ (and therefore $pi(2+2mathbb{Z})= 0$) and so on for every coset but then you will find out that $pi$ is no longer a homomorphism. Indeed, let's simplify notation, I will use $[x]$ instead of $x+I$. In our case $R/I={[0],[1]}$. Note that we have $[1]+[1]=[0]$. Put for example $pi([0])=0$ and $pi([1])=1$. Then



      $$pi([1]+[1])=pi([0])=0$$
      $$pi([1])+pi([1])=1+1=2$$



      and so $pi$ is not a homomorphism. And in this particular case there is no way to fix that. The only choice of values making $phi$ a homomorphism is $pi([x])=0$. Not to mention that $R/I$ has two elements while $R$ is infinite so there's no chance for $pi$ to be surjective.



      So as you can see there are no shortcuts. Also the existence of an isomorphism $R/Isimeq R$ for $Ineq 0$ is a very rare situation. First of all if $R$ is nontrivial then $R/R$ is trivial. If you are looking for an example of proper ideal then consider $R$ which is not simple (so it has a proper, nontrivial ideal). Then there's always a proper quotient $R/I$ not isomorphic to $R$, namely for any maximal ideal $I$.






      share|cite|improve this answer











      $endgroup$



      Your $pi$ is not a function in general. For example consider $R=mathbb{Z}$ and $I=2mathbb{Z}$. Then $0+2mathbb{Z}=2+2mathbb{Z}$. So what is $pi(0+2mathbb{Z})=pi(2+2mathbb{Z})$? Is it $0$ or $2$?



      Of course you can arbitrarly choose for example $pi(0+2mathbb{Z}):= 0$ (and therefore $pi(2+2mathbb{Z})= 0$) and so on for every coset but then you will find out that $pi$ is no longer a homomorphism. Indeed, let's simplify notation, I will use $[x]$ instead of $x+I$. In our case $R/I={[0],[1]}$. Note that we have $[1]+[1]=[0]$. Put for example $pi([0])=0$ and $pi([1])=1$. Then



      $$pi([1]+[1])=pi([0])=0$$
      $$pi([1])+pi([1])=1+1=2$$



      and so $pi$ is not a homomorphism. And in this particular case there is no way to fix that. The only choice of values making $phi$ a homomorphism is $pi([x])=0$. Not to mention that $R/I$ has two elements while $R$ is infinite so there's no chance for $pi$ to be surjective.



      So as you can see there are no shortcuts. Also the existence of an isomorphism $R/Isimeq R$ for $Ineq 0$ is a very rare situation. First of all if $R$ is nontrivial then $R/R$ is trivial. If you are looking for an example of proper ideal then consider $R$ which is not simple (so it has a proper, nontrivial ideal). Then there's always a proper quotient $R/I$ not isomorphic to $R$, namely for any maximal ideal $I$.







      share|cite|improve this answer














      share|cite|improve this answer



      share|cite|improve this answer








      edited Dec 21 '18 at 16:03

























      answered Dec 21 '18 at 11:09









      freakishfreakish

      12.4k1630




      12.4k1630












      • $begingroup$
        So after writing out a lot of stuff, I just came to the conclusion that maps going from the quotient $R/I$ to $R$ usually come with a lot of problems as opposed to defining $R to R/I$.
        $endgroup$
        – Hawk
        Dec 21 '18 at 12:30










      • $begingroup$
        @Hawk yes, the situation is not symmetric at all.
        $endgroup$
        – freakish
        Dec 21 '18 at 12:31










      • $begingroup$
        No what i mean is that if I had defined it $pi: R to R/I$, it would be easier to prove it is an isomorphism and to identify the problems, which in this case is well-definedness.
        $endgroup$
        – Hawk
        Dec 21 '18 at 12:33


















      • $begingroup$
        So after writing out a lot of stuff, I just came to the conclusion that maps going from the quotient $R/I$ to $R$ usually come with a lot of problems as opposed to defining $R to R/I$.
        $endgroup$
        – Hawk
        Dec 21 '18 at 12:30










      • $begingroup$
        @Hawk yes, the situation is not symmetric at all.
        $endgroup$
        – freakish
        Dec 21 '18 at 12:31










      • $begingroup$
        No what i mean is that if I had defined it $pi: R to R/I$, it would be easier to prove it is an isomorphism and to identify the problems, which in this case is well-definedness.
        $endgroup$
        – Hawk
        Dec 21 '18 at 12:33
















      $begingroup$
      So after writing out a lot of stuff, I just came to the conclusion that maps going from the quotient $R/I$ to $R$ usually come with a lot of problems as opposed to defining $R to R/I$.
      $endgroup$
      – Hawk
      Dec 21 '18 at 12:30




      $begingroup$
      So after writing out a lot of stuff, I just came to the conclusion that maps going from the quotient $R/I$ to $R$ usually come with a lot of problems as opposed to defining $R to R/I$.
      $endgroup$
      – Hawk
      Dec 21 '18 at 12:30












      $begingroup$
      @Hawk yes, the situation is not symmetric at all.
      $endgroup$
      – freakish
      Dec 21 '18 at 12:31




      $begingroup$
      @Hawk yes, the situation is not symmetric at all.
      $endgroup$
      – freakish
      Dec 21 '18 at 12:31












      $begingroup$
      No what i mean is that if I had defined it $pi: R to R/I$, it would be easier to prove it is an isomorphism and to identify the problems, which in this case is well-definedness.
      $endgroup$
      – Hawk
      Dec 21 '18 at 12:33




      $begingroup$
      No what i mean is that if I had defined it $pi: R to R/I$, it would be easier to prove it is an isomorphism and to identify the problems, which in this case is well-definedness.
      $endgroup$
      – Hawk
      Dec 21 '18 at 12:33











      1












      $begingroup$

      Your function $pi$ is only well-defined if $I$ is the ideal ${0}$. E.g., with $R = Bbb{Z}$ and $I = 2Bbb{Z}$, we have $1 + I = 3 + I$, so if $pi(a + I) = a $, we would have to have $1 = 3$, which holds in $R/I$, but does not hold in $R$.






      share|cite|improve this answer









      $endgroup$


















        1












        $begingroup$

        Your function $pi$ is only well-defined if $I$ is the ideal ${0}$. E.g., with $R = Bbb{Z}$ and $I = 2Bbb{Z}$, we have $1 + I = 3 + I$, so if $pi(a + I) = a $, we would have to have $1 = 3$, which holds in $R/I$, but does not hold in $R$.






        share|cite|improve this answer









        $endgroup$
















          1












          1








          1





          $begingroup$

          Your function $pi$ is only well-defined if $I$ is the ideal ${0}$. E.g., with $R = Bbb{Z}$ and $I = 2Bbb{Z}$, we have $1 + I = 3 + I$, so if $pi(a + I) = a $, we would have to have $1 = 3$, which holds in $R/I$, but does not hold in $R$.






          share|cite|improve this answer









          $endgroup$



          Your function $pi$ is only well-defined if $I$ is the ideal ${0}$. E.g., with $R = Bbb{Z}$ and $I = 2Bbb{Z}$, we have $1 + I = 3 + I$, so if $pi(a + I) = a $, we would have to have $1 = 3$, which holds in $R/I$, but does not hold in $R$.







          share|cite|improve this answer












          share|cite|improve this answer



          share|cite|improve this answer










          answered Dec 21 '18 at 11:10









          Rob ArthanRob Arthan

          29.3k42966




          29.3k42966























              0












              $begingroup$

              For each $ain R$ there are several $bin R$ such that $a+I=b+I$ (unless $I={0}$ in the first place). So it is unclear what $a$ you are referring to.






              share|cite|improve this answer











              $endgroup$


















                0












                $begingroup$

                For each $ain R$ there are several $bin R$ such that $a+I=b+I$ (unless $I={0}$ in the first place). So it is unclear what $a$ you are referring to.






                share|cite|improve this answer











                $endgroup$
















                  0












                  0








                  0





                  $begingroup$

                  For each $ain R$ there are several $bin R$ such that $a+I=b+I$ (unless $I={0}$ in the first place). So it is unclear what $a$ you are referring to.






                  share|cite|improve this answer











                  $endgroup$



                  For each $ain R$ there are several $bin R$ such that $a+I=b+I$ (unless $I={0}$ in the first place). So it is unclear what $a$ you are referring to.







                  share|cite|improve this answer














                  share|cite|improve this answer



                  share|cite|improve this answer








                  edited Dec 21 '18 at 11:14

























                  answered Dec 21 '18 at 11:09









                  Saucy O'PathSaucy O'Path

                  5,9791627




                  5,9791627






























                      draft saved

                      draft discarded




















































                      Thanks for contributing an answer to Mathematics Stack Exchange!


                      • Please be sure to answer the question. Provide details and share your research!

                      But avoid



                      • Asking for help, clarification, or responding to other answers.

                      • Making statements based on opinion; back them up with references or personal experience.


                      Use MathJax to format equations. MathJax reference.


                      To learn more, see our tips on writing great answers.




                      draft saved


                      draft discarded














                      StackExchange.ready(
                      function () {
                      StackExchange.openid.initPostLogin('.new-post-login', 'https%3a%2f%2fmath.stackexchange.com%2fquestions%2f3048398%2fwhat-is-wrong-with-this-argument-r-i-approx-r%23new-answer', 'question_page');
                      }
                      );

                      Post as a guest















                      Required, but never shown





















































                      Required, but never shown














                      Required, but never shown












                      Required, but never shown







                      Required, but never shown

































                      Required, but never shown














                      Required, but never shown












                      Required, but never shown







                      Required, but never shown







                      Popular posts from this blog

                      Quarter-circle Tiles

                      build a pushdown automaton that recognizes the reverse language of a given pushdown automaton?

                      Mont Emei