Kähler manifolds are formal
$begingroup$
I want to understand why Kähler manifolds are formal.
This was first proved by Deligne, Griffiths, Morgan, Sullivan
Let $mathcal M$ be a minimal differential
algebra and $H^*(mathcal M)$ the cohomology
of $mathcal M$, viewed as a
differential algebra with $d =0$.
Definition.
$mathcal M$ is formal if there is a map of differential algebras $psi: mathcal M to H^*(mathcal M)$ inducing the identity
on cohomology.
- The homotopy type of a differential
algebra $mathcal A$ is a formal consequence of its cohomology if its minimal model is formal.
- The real (or complex) homotopy
type of a manifold $M$ is a formal consequence of the
cohomology $M$ if the de Rham homotopy type of the real (or
complex) forms
$mathcal E$ is a formal consequence of its cohomology.
In section 6, the following (main) theorem is proved:
Let $M$ be a compact complex manifold for which the
$dd^c$-lemma holds (e.g. $M$ Kähler, or $M$ a Moisezon space).
Then the real homotopy type of $M$ is a formal consequence of
the cohomology ring $H^*(M; mathbb R)$
Let ${mathcal E^*_M,d}$ be the de-Rham complex on $M$, ${mathcal E^c_M,d}$ the subcomplex of $d^c$-closed forms and ${H_{d^c},d}$ the quotient complex $mathcal E_M^c/d^c mathcal E_M$.
Using the $dd^c$-lemma ($partial barpartial$-lemma), it is an easy calculation, that the natural maps
$${mathcal E^*_M,d} stackrel ileftarrow {mathcal E^c_M,d} stackrel pto {H_{d^c},d} $$
are quasi-isomorphisms and that the differential on $H_{d^c}(M)$ vanishes.
In the proof, the theorem follows immediately from the above. I don't see how and I am a little confused that there were no reasons given why the theorem follows. Only "This proves the claim and consequently [part (1)] of the theorem".
The maps seem to be maps of differential algebras, so this is fine.
But as far as I see, the theorem only follows if we can replace ${H_{d^c},d=0}$ with ${H_M,d=0}$.
Update/ Solution:
I repeat: The theorem only follows if we can replace ${H_{d^c},d=0}$ with ${H_M,d=0}$.
But the above argument shows, that the cohomologies are isomorphic. More precisely, the isomorphism is induced by $i$ and $p$.
abstract-algebra algebraic-topology homology-cohomology homotopy-theory complex-geometry
$endgroup$
add a comment |
$begingroup$
I want to understand why Kähler manifolds are formal.
This was first proved by Deligne, Griffiths, Morgan, Sullivan
Let $mathcal M$ be a minimal differential
algebra and $H^*(mathcal M)$ the cohomology
of $mathcal M$, viewed as a
differential algebra with $d =0$.
Definition.
$mathcal M$ is formal if there is a map of differential algebras $psi: mathcal M to H^*(mathcal M)$ inducing the identity
on cohomology.
- The homotopy type of a differential
algebra $mathcal A$ is a formal consequence of its cohomology if its minimal model is formal.
- The real (or complex) homotopy
type of a manifold $M$ is a formal consequence of the
cohomology $M$ if the de Rham homotopy type of the real (or
complex) forms
$mathcal E$ is a formal consequence of its cohomology.
In section 6, the following (main) theorem is proved:
Let $M$ be a compact complex manifold for which the
$dd^c$-lemma holds (e.g. $M$ Kähler, or $M$ a Moisezon space).
Then the real homotopy type of $M$ is a formal consequence of
the cohomology ring $H^*(M; mathbb R)$
Let ${mathcal E^*_M,d}$ be the de-Rham complex on $M$, ${mathcal E^c_M,d}$ the subcomplex of $d^c$-closed forms and ${H_{d^c},d}$ the quotient complex $mathcal E_M^c/d^c mathcal E_M$.
Using the $dd^c$-lemma ($partial barpartial$-lemma), it is an easy calculation, that the natural maps
$${mathcal E^*_M,d} stackrel ileftarrow {mathcal E^c_M,d} stackrel pto {H_{d^c},d} $$
are quasi-isomorphisms and that the differential on $H_{d^c}(M)$ vanishes.
In the proof, the theorem follows immediately from the above. I don't see how and I am a little confused that there were no reasons given why the theorem follows. Only "This proves the claim and consequently [part (1)] of the theorem".
The maps seem to be maps of differential algebras, so this is fine.
But as far as I see, the theorem only follows if we can replace ${H_{d^c},d=0}$ with ${H_M,d=0}$.
Update/ Solution:
I repeat: The theorem only follows if we can replace ${H_{d^c},d=0}$ with ${H_M,d=0}$.
But the above argument shows, that the cohomologies are isomorphic. More precisely, the isomorphism is induced by $i$ and $p$.
abstract-algebra algebraic-topology homology-cohomology homotopy-theory complex-geometry
$endgroup$
add a comment |
$begingroup$
I want to understand why Kähler manifolds are formal.
This was first proved by Deligne, Griffiths, Morgan, Sullivan
Let $mathcal M$ be a minimal differential
algebra and $H^*(mathcal M)$ the cohomology
of $mathcal M$, viewed as a
differential algebra with $d =0$.
Definition.
$mathcal M$ is formal if there is a map of differential algebras $psi: mathcal M to H^*(mathcal M)$ inducing the identity
on cohomology.
- The homotopy type of a differential
algebra $mathcal A$ is a formal consequence of its cohomology if its minimal model is formal.
- The real (or complex) homotopy
type of a manifold $M$ is a formal consequence of the
cohomology $M$ if the de Rham homotopy type of the real (or
complex) forms
$mathcal E$ is a formal consequence of its cohomology.
In section 6, the following (main) theorem is proved:
Let $M$ be a compact complex manifold for which the
$dd^c$-lemma holds (e.g. $M$ Kähler, or $M$ a Moisezon space).
Then the real homotopy type of $M$ is a formal consequence of
the cohomology ring $H^*(M; mathbb R)$
Let ${mathcal E^*_M,d}$ be the de-Rham complex on $M$, ${mathcal E^c_M,d}$ the subcomplex of $d^c$-closed forms and ${H_{d^c},d}$ the quotient complex $mathcal E_M^c/d^c mathcal E_M$.
Using the $dd^c$-lemma ($partial barpartial$-lemma), it is an easy calculation, that the natural maps
$${mathcal E^*_M,d} stackrel ileftarrow {mathcal E^c_M,d} stackrel pto {H_{d^c},d} $$
are quasi-isomorphisms and that the differential on $H_{d^c}(M)$ vanishes.
In the proof, the theorem follows immediately from the above. I don't see how and I am a little confused that there were no reasons given why the theorem follows. Only "This proves the claim and consequently [part (1)] of the theorem".
The maps seem to be maps of differential algebras, so this is fine.
But as far as I see, the theorem only follows if we can replace ${H_{d^c},d=0}$ with ${H_M,d=0}$.
Update/ Solution:
I repeat: The theorem only follows if we can replace ${H_{d^c},d=0}$ with ${H_M,d=0}$.
But the above argument shows, that the cohomologies are isomorphic. More precisely, the isomorphism is induced by $i$ and $p$.
abstract-algebra algebraic-topology homology-cohomology homotopy-theory complex-geometry
$endgroup$
I want to understand why Kähler manifolds are formal.
This was first proved by Deligne, Griffiths, Morgan, Sullivan
Let $mathcal M$ be a minimal differential
algebra and $H^*(mathcal M)$ the cohomology
of $mathcal M$, viewed as a
differential algebra with $d =0$.
Definition.
$mathcal M$ is formal if there is a map of differential algebras $psi: mathcal M to H^*(mathcal M)$ inducing the identity
on cohomology.
- The homotopy type of a differential
algebra $mathcal A$ is a formal consequence of its cohomology if its minimal model is formal.
- The real (or complex) homotopy
type of a manifold $M$ is a formal consequence of the
cohomology $M$ if the de Rham homotopy type of the real (or
complex) forms
$mathcal E$ is a formal consequence of its cohomology.
In section 6, the following (main) theorem is proved:
Let $M$ be a compact complex manifold for which the
$dd^c$-lemma holds (e.g. $M$ Kähler, or $M$ a Moisezon space).
Then the real homotopy type of $M$ is a formal consequence of
the cohomology ring $H^*(M; mathbb R)$
Let ${mathcal E^*_M,d}$ be the de-Rham complex on $M$, ${mathcal E^c_M,d}$ the subcomplex of $d^c$-closed forms and ${H_{d^c},d}$ the quotient complex $mathcal E_M^c/d^c mathcal E_M$.
Using the $dd^c$-lemma ($partial barpartial$-lemma), it is an easy calculation, that the natural maps
$${mathcal E^*_M,d} stackrel ileftarrow {mathcal E^c_M,d} stackrel pto {H_{d^c},d} $$
are quasi-isomorphisms and that the differential on $H_{d^c}(M)$ vanishes.
In the proof, the theorem follows immediately from the above. I don't see how and I am a little confused that there were no reasons given why the theorem follows. Only "This proves the claim and consequently [part (1)] of the theorem".
The maps seem to be maps of differential algebras, so this is fine.
But as far as I see, the theorem only follows if we can replace ${H_{d^c},d=0}$ with ${H_M,d=0}$.
Update/ Solution:
I repeat: The theorem only follows if we can replace ${H_{d^c},d=0}$ with ${H_M,d=0}$.
But the above argument shows, that the cohomologies are isomorphic. More precisely, the isomorphism is induced by $i$ and $p$.
abstract-algebra algebraic-topology homology-cohomology homotopy-theory complex-geometry
abstract-algebra algebraic-topology homology-cohomology homotopy-theory complex-geometry
edited Dec 7 '18 at 23:29
klirk
asked Dec 7 '18 at 19:16
klirkklirk
2,631530
2,631530
add a comment |
add a comment |
1 Answer
1
active
oldest
votes
$begingroup$
A dg-algebra with vanishing differential is its own cohomology. The morphisms $i_*,rho_*$ are isomorphisms between the cohomology of $(mathscr{E}^*_M,d)$ -- which is $H^*(M)$ -- and the cohomology of $(H_{d^c}, d = 0)$ -- which is $H_{d^c}$, because the differential vanishes.
More generally if a dg-algebra $A$ is quasi-isomorphic to any dg-algebra $B$ with vanishing differential, then $B$ is isomorphic to the cohomology of $A$, pretty much by definition; hence $A$ is formal.
$endgroup$
$begingroup$
Thank you. I already had everything in mind what you said, for some reason I just failed to make the last (surprisingly easy) step. It's clear now.
$endgroup$
– klirk
Dec 7 '18 at 23:21
add a comment |
Your Answer
StackExchange.ifUsing("editor", function () {
return StackExchange.using("mathjaxEditing", function () {
StackExchange.MarkdownEditor.creationCallbacks.add(function (editor, postfix) {
StackExchange.mathjaxEditing.prepareWmdForMathJax(editor, postfix, [["$", "$"], ["\\(","\\)"]]);
});
});
}, "mathjax-editing");
StackExchange.ready(function() {
var channelOptions = {
tags: "".split(" "),
id: "69"
};
initTagRenderer("".split(" "), "".split(" "), channelOptions);
StackExchange.using("externalEditor", function() {
// Have to fire editor after snippets, if snippets enabled
if (StackExchange.settings.snippets.snippetsEnabled) {
StackExchange.using("snippets", function() {
createEditor();
});
}
else {
createEditor();
}
});
function createEditor() {
StackExchange.prepareEditor({
heartbeatType: 'answer',
autoActivateHeartbeat: false,
convertImagesToLinks: true,
noModals: true,
showLowRepImageUploadWarning: true,
reputationToPostImages: 10,
bindNavPrevention: true,
postfix: "",
imageUploader: {
brandingHtml: "Powered by u003ca class="icon-imgur-white" href="https://imgur.com/"u003eu003c/au003e",
contentPolicyHtml: "User contributions licensed under u003ca href="https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-sa/3.0/"u003ecc by-sa 3.0 with attribution requiredu003c/au003e u003ca href="https://stackoverflow.com/legal/content-policy"u003e(content policy)u003c/au003e",
allowUrls: true
},
noCode: true, onDemand: true,
discardSelector: ".discard-answer"
,immediatelyShowMarkdownHelp:true
});
}
});
Sign up or log in
StackExchange.ready(function () {
StackExchange.helpers.onClickDraftSave('#login-link');
});
Sign up using Google
Sign up using Facebook
Sign up using Email and Password
Post as a guest
Required, but never shown
StackExchange.ready(
function () {
StackExchange.openid.initPostLogin('.new-post-login', 'https%3a%2f%2fmath.stackexchange.com%2fquestions%2f3030268%2fk%25c3%25a4hler-manifolds-are-formal%23new-answer', 'question_page');
}
);
Post as a guest
Required, but never shown
1 Answer
1
active
oldest
votes
1 Answer
1
active
oldest
votes
active
oldest
votes
active
oldest
votes
$begingroup$
A dg-algebra with vanishing differential is its own cohomology. The morphisms $i_*,rho_*$ are isomorphisms between the cohomology of $(mathscr{E}^*_M,d)$ -- which is $H^*(M)$ -- and the cohomology of $(H_{d^c}, d = 0)$ -- which is $H_{d^c}$, because the differential vanishes.
More generally if a dg-algebra $A$ is quasi-isomorphic to any dg-algebra $B$ with vanishing differential, then $B$ is isomorphic to the cohomology of $A$, pretty much by definition; hence $A$ is formal.
$endgroup$
$begingroup$
Thank you. I already had everything in mind what you said, for some reason I just failed to make the last (surprisingly easy) step. It's clear now.
$endgroup$
– klirk
Dec 7 '18 at 23:21
add a comment |
$begingroup$
A dg-algebra with vanishing differential is its own cohomology. The morphisms $i_*,rho_*$ are isomorphisms between the cohomology of $(mathscr{E}^*_M,d)$ -- which is $H^*(M)$ -- and the cohomology of $(H_{d^c}, d = 0)$ -- which is $H_{d^c}$, because the differential vanishes.
More generally if a dg-algebra $A$ is quasi-isomorphic to any dg-algebra $B$ with vanishing differential, then $B$ is isomorphic to the cohomology of $A$, pretty much by definition; hence $A$ is formal.
$endgroup$
$begingroup$
Thank you. I already had everything in mind what you said, for some reason I just failed to make the last (surprisingly easy) step. It's clear now.
$endgroup$
– klirk
Dec 7 '18 at 23:21
add a comment |
$begingroup$
A dg-algebra with vanishing differential is its own cohomology. The morphisms $i_*,rho_*$ are isomorphisms between the cohomology of $(mathscr{E}^*_M,d)$ -- which is $H^*(M)$ -- and the cohomology of $(H_{d^c}, d = 0)$ -- which is $H_{d^c}$, because the differential vanishes.
More generally if a dg-algebra $A$ is quasi-isomorphic to any dg-algebra $B$ with vanishing differential, then $B$ is isomorphic to the cohomology of $A$, pretty much by definition; hence $A$ is formal.
$endgroup$
A dg-algebra with vanishing differential is its own cohomology. The morphisms $i_*,rho_*$ are isomorphisms between the cohomology of $(mathscr{E}^*_M,d)$ -- which is $H^*(M)$ -- and the cohomology of $(H_{d^c}, d = 0)$ -- which is $H_{d^c}$, because the differential vanishes.
More generally if a dg-algebra $A$ is quasi-isomorphic to any dg-algebra $B$ with vanishing differential, then $B$ is isomorphic to the cohomology of $A$, pretty much by definition; hence $A$ is formal.
answered Dec 7 '18 at 20:39
Najib IdrissiNajib Idrissi
41k471139
41k471139
$begingroup$
Thank you. I already had everything in mind what you said, for some reason I just failed to make the last (surprisingly easy) step. It's clear now.
$endgroup$
– klirk
Dec 7 '18 at 23:21
add a comment |
$begingroup$
Thank you. I already had everything in mind what you said, for some reason I just failed to make the last (surprisingly easy) step. It's clear now.
$endgroup$
– klirk
Dec 7 '18 at 23:21
$begingroup$
Thank you. I already had everything in mind what you said, for some reason I just failed to make the last (surprisingly easy) step. It's clear now.
$endgroup$
– klirk
Dec 7 '18 at 23:21
$begingroup$
Thank you. I already had everything in mind what you said, for some reason I just failed to make the last (surprisingly easy) step. It's clear now.
$endgroup$
– klirk
Dec 7 '18 at 23:21
add a comment |
Thanks for contributing an answer to Mathematics Stack Exchange!
- Please be sure to answer the question. Provide details and share your research!
But avoid …
- Asking for help, clarification, or responding to other answers.
- Making statements based on opinion; back them up with references or personal experience.
Use MathJax to format equations. MathJax reference.
To learn more, see our tips on writing great answers.
Sign up or log in
StackExchange.ready(function () {
StackExchange.helpers.onClickDraftSave('#login-link');
});
Sign up using Google
Sign up using Facebook
Sign up using Email and Password
Post as a guest
Required, but never shown
StackExchange.ready(
function () {
StackExchange.openid.initPostLogin('.new-post-login', 'https%3a%2f%2fmath.stackexchange.com%2fquestions%2f3030268%2fk%25c3%25a4hler-manifolds-are-formal%23new-answer', 'question_page');
}
);
Post as a guest
Required, but never shown
Sign up or log in
StackExchange.ready(function () {
StackExchange.helpers.onClickDraftSave('#login-link');
});
Sign up using Google
Sign up using Facebook
Sign up using Email and Password
Post as a guest
Required, but never shown
Sign up or log in
StackExchange.ready(function () {
StackExchange.helpers.onClickDraftSave('#login-link');
});
Sign up using Google
Sign up using Facebook
Sign up using Email and Password
Post as a guest
Required, but never shown
Sign up or log in
StackExchange.ready(function () {
StackExchange.helpers.onClickDraftSave('#login-link');
});
Sign up using Google
Sign up using Facebook
Sign up using Email and Password
Sign up using Google
Sign up using Facebook
Sign up using Email and Password
Post as a guest
Required, but never shown
Required, but never shown
Required, but never shown
Required, but never shown
Required, but never shown
Required, but never shown
Required, but never shown
Required, but never shown
Required, but never shown